The Moral Case Against the
Iraq War
by Paul Savoy
The Nation magazine, May
31, 2004
As the Iraq war continues into its second
year, the Bush Administration's reasons for being there are more
indefensible than ever; Prewar claims regarding Iraq's weapons
of mass destruction have all proved to be wrong; the number of
terrorists in Iraq has increased rather than decreased; more American
troops were killed in April than were lost during the entire invasion
phase of the war; the systemic and barbarous abuse of Iraqi detainees
contradicts the most basic values the Administration claimed it
would bring to Iraq; and the uprisings in Falluja and at least
half a dozen other cities portend a nationwide insurgency by both
Sunnis and Shiites against the US presence. Yet the latest polls-including
one conducted after the revelations about the torture of Iraqi
prisoners-show that about half of Americans remain convinced that
the war was morally justified. President Bush, in a speech on
March 19 marking the first anniversary of the conflict, articulated
a moral defense of the war that has been repeated many times:
"No one can argue that the Iraqi people would be better off"
with Saddam Hussein's regime "back in the palaces."
Even those who opposed the war have, up to now, found the President's
moral argument difficult to answer. The Indian novelist Arundhati
Roy, in a speech to this year's session of the World Social Forum
in Bombay, lamented how "plenty of antiwar activists have
retreated in confusion since the capture of Saddam Hussein. Isn't
the world better off without Saddam Hussein? they ask timidly"
The problem opponents of the war have
had in responding to President Bush's claim of moral legitimacy,
as University of California linguistics professor George Lakoff
suggests, is that they have addressed the moral issue in the terms
the President has framed it rather than reframing the issue in
their own moral terms. Talking about the world, or at least Iraq,
being "better off" avoids confronting the civilian carnage
caused by the war. As the late Robert Nozick cautioned in his
classic work on the moral basis of freedom, Anarchy, State, and
Utopia, we should be wary of talking about the overall good of
society or of a particular country. There is no social entity
called Iraq that benefited from some self-sacrifice it suffered
for its own greater good, like a patient who voluntarily endures
some pain to be better off than before. There were only individual
human beings living in Iraq before the war, with their individual
lives. Sacrificing the lives of some of them for the benefit of
others killed them and benefited the others. Nothing more. Each
of those Iraqis killed in the war was a separate person, and the
unfinished life each of them lost was the only life he or she
had, or would ever have. They clearly are not better off now that
Saddam is gone from power.
There is only one truly serious question
about the morality of the war, and that is the question posed
more than fifty years ago by French Nobel laureate Albert Camus,
looking back on two world wars that had slaughtered more than
70 million people: When do we have the right to kill our fellow
human beings or let them be killed? What is needed is a national
debate in the presidential election campaign that addresses the
most important moral issue of our time. It is an issue we are
required to face not only as a matter of moral obligation to all
those Iraqis killed in the war, but to the 772 American servicemen
and -women who, as of May 10, had lost their lives and the more
than 4,000 US soldiers injured in Iraq. The debate should begin
by moving beyond the narrow factual focus on WMD intelligence
to an examination of the broad moral principles and values governing
the use of deadly force against other human beings. Those principles
are to be found in the basic precepts of our more than 200-year-old
constitutional tradition and criminal jurisprudence, and in widely
accepted standards of international humanitarian law.
Reliable estimates by independent organizations
indicate that more civilians died in the first month of the war
than were killed in the September 11 attack on the World Trade
Center. A five-week investigation by the Associated Press reported
at _ least 3,240 civilian deaths between March 20 and April 20,
2003, including 1,896 in Baghdad alone. The AP survey notes that
"hundreds, possibly thousands, of victims" are not reflected
in the totals because the count excluded victims not taken to
hospitals as well as records of hospitals in areas too remote
or dangerous to visit. Between April 20, 2003, and the beginning
of the wider insurgency almost a year later, at least 500 Iraqi
civilians were reported by Iraq's Interior Ministry to have been
killed by American-led forces in checkpoint shootings, misdirected
arms fire and delayed explosions of cluster bombs. Hundreds more
have been killed in the siege of Falluja, according to the director
of the city's general hospital.
But even if as many as 5,000 civilians
have been killed by US forces, isn't freedom for 25 million people
in Iraq worth the cost of 5,000 lives? Michael Ignatieff, director
of the Carr Center for Human Rights Policy at Harvard, argued
this cost-benefit analysis in making the moral case for war in
the New York Times Magazine before the invasion: "The choice
[was] one between two evils, between containing and leaving a
tyrant in place and the targeted use of force, which will kill
people but free a nation from the tyrant's grip." Ignatieff
concluded that killing people was the better choice if the United
States was willing "to build freedom, not just for the Iraqis
but also for the Palestinians, along with a greater sense of security
for Israel."
This is the moral reasoning of Raskolnikov
in Dostoyevsky's Crime and Punishment. Invoking the lesser-of-two-evils
defense to justify his killing an old pawnbroker and stealing
her money, Raskolnikov argues: "Kill her, take her money,
dedicate it to serving mankind, to the general welfare. Well-what
do you think- isn't this petty little crime effaced by thousands
of good deeds? For one life, thousands of lives saved from ruin
and collapse. One death and a hundred lives-there's arithmetic
for you." A few thousand dead Iraqis and freedom for 25 million.
What is overlooked by those who believe
the benefits of the war outweigh the costs is that killing even
one innocent person to benefit others violates the most basic
human right-the right to life. The right to life is one of those
unalienable rights enshrined in the Declaration of Independence
and the Bill of Rights. "Life is the immediate gift of God"
a right inherent by nature in every individual," William
Blackstone wrote in his eighteenth-century
Commentaries on the Laws of England, one
of the leading sources of American civil liberties. What Blackstone
meant when he characterized the right to life as a God-given right
is that it is beyond the power of any mere government to abrogate
or repeal. Innocent people may not be killed or injured by the
state, even when a majority believes it serves the greater good.
In a prelude to the "Grand Inquisitor"
scene in The Brothers Karamazov, Ivan asks his faith-based brother
Alyosha a question we all need to ask ourselves about the children
who were killed or injured in the Iraq war: "Let's assume
that you were called upon to build the edifice of human destiny
so that men would finally be happy and would find peace and tranquillity.
If you knew that, in order to attain this, you would have to torture
just one single creature, let's say the little girl who beat her
chest so desperately in the outhouse, and that on her unavenged
tears you could build that edifice, would you agree to do it?"
Even more horrifying than the torture
of Iraqi prisoners by their American captors has been the unnecessary
suffering and death inflicted on the Iraqi people by the war itself.
One of those children on whose unavenged tears the edifice of
freedom has been built in Iraq was 12-year-old Ali Ismael Abbas,
who was so badly burned in a US missile attack on Baghdad that
his entire torso was black, his arms so mutilated that, as New
Yorker correspondent Jon Lee Anderson described the hospital scene,
they "looked like something that might be found in a barbecue
pit." His family, which included his pregnant mother, his
father and his six brothers and sisters, were all killed by the
blast. Some of their bodies were so unrecognizable that all Anderson
could see in morgue photographs was a collection of charred body
parts and some red flesh. The remains of other family members
were mutilated grotesqueries. "[His mother's] face had been
cut in half, as if by a giant cleaver, and her mouth was yawning
open.... The body of his brother was all there, it seemed, but
from the nose up his head was gone, simply sheared off, like the
head of a rubber doll. His mouth, like that of his mother, was
open, as if he were screaming." Judging from the poll numbers
after the fall of the Iraqi regime, the seven or eight out of
ten Americans who backed the war were prepared to build the edifice
of freedom and democracy on the broken bodies not of one, but
of hundreds, possibly thousands, of Iraqi children killed or maimed
or burned in the conflict.
Viewed in the light of our own moral ideals,
as embodied in our constitutional tradition, the right to life
is so fundamental that killing the innocent to advance the cause
of freedom of electoral choice or any other purpose, however worthy,
must be regarded as wrong. We denounce terrorists because when
the freedom of self-determination they seek is weighed in the
balance against the right to life of innocent people, it is the
right to life that our collective conscience has decided should
prevail. Terrorism is simply a criminal technique for coercing
a political agenda by killing innocent people. And it should make
no difference whether the people who do the killing are freedom
fighters like Palestinian suicide bombers, who purposefully kill
civilians, or freedom fighters like the American liberators of
the Iraqi people, who aim at military targets but who know with
substantial certainty that they will incidentally kill civilians.
In the eyes of the criminal law, a person is regarded as intending
the death of another when he either has the purpose to cause the
death of the victim or when he knows that death is substantially
certain to result from his acts.
Gen. Richard Myers, chairman of the Joint
Chiefs of Staff, warned before the war that, despite the military's
best efforts to prevent civilian casualties, 'people are going
to die." Given this knowledge aforethought, the Administration
cannot continue to pretend that the civilian deaths in Iraq were
accidental. The mother killed in a Baghdad bomb blast holding
her baby so tightly they could not be pried apart, and the thousands
of other innocent Iraqis killed in the war, were the victims of
intentional homicide, however accidental or acceptable their deaths
may have appeared on Fox News or CNN.
There is one exception to the prohibition
against taking innocent human life, recognized by both our own
principles of criminal jurisprudence and international rules of
warfare. Deadly force may be used in self-defense even when innocent
people will be killed in the combat required to defeat the aggressor.
Although international rules of warfare prohibit the purposeful
targeting of civilians, even in a defensive war, the law makes
an exception for the incidental or "collateral" killing
of the innocent because civilian casualties are frequently unavoidable
in mounting an effective military operation against the enemy.
However, when a nation acts in self-defense
before it is actually attacked international law requires an imminent
threat. As statements by CIA director George Tenet have made clear,
the White House did not even have probable cause to believe its
own prewar claims, both express and implied that the danger was
imminent. Intelligence analysts "never said there was an
'imminent threat," Tenet insisted in a February 5 speech
at Georgetown University defending his agency. But according to
the President, the United States had the right to go to war on
a lesser standard than imminence. The Administration's position,
first announced in its 2002 National Security Strategy, is that
military force can be used pre-emptively whenever a threat, however
remote or improbable, involves the use of chemical, biological
or nuclear weapons. As President Bush argued in a February 8 interview
with NBC's Tim Russert, "It is essential that when we see
a threat, we deal with those threats before they become imminent.
It's too late if they become imminent."
The elimination of the longstanding requirement
of imminence by the Bush doctrine of pre-emption has been roundly
condemned by UN Secretary General Kofi Annan, who called it a
"fundamental challenge to the principles on which, however
imperfectly, world peace and stability have rested for the last
fifty-eight years." But for many Americans living in the
shadow of September 11, common sense and simple prudence seemed
to dictate a policy that says, in effect, we should kill them
before they can kill us. What critics of the Bush doctrine failed
to make clear is that the concept of imminence is essential because
it actualizes the most basic moral principle upon which not only
the United Nations Charter but our own constitutional system of
government, is based: the sanctity of innocent human life.
The self-defense exception to the general
principle protecting innocent life is not based on any cost-benefit
calculation. Rather, the killing of innocent people is excused
as a concession to human weakness. Self-defense in the face of
an imminent threat of being killed is what Justice Oliver Wendell
Holmes called one of those "can't helps" of life. No
community of human beings facing an immediate threat of attack
can reasonably be expected to allow themselves to be killed in
order to avoid killing innocent people in the aggressor nation.
Such extraordinary self-sacrifice is not demanded of ordinary
mortals.
But when a threat is not imminent in the
sense that there is sufficient time to protect ourselves without
killing innocent people- by using more rigorous weapons inspections,
for example-we lack that "can't help" that Justice Holmes
suggested was a condition for sacrificing human life in a civilized
society. To say, as the President continues to insist, that he
had "no choice" is to make the absurd and horrific claim
that he had no choice but to kill thousands of innocent people.
We reply that the moral principles contained in our criminal and
constitutional jurisprudence forbid the use of war to check tyrants
and terrorists who threaten us with death unless there is such
a clear and present danger to the nation that taking the lives
of innocent men, women and children is the only way we can save
our own lives.
The final argument advanced by the Administration,
as well as some human rights advocates, is that the war was morally
justifiable as a humanitarian intervention to defend the Iraqi
people from mass slaughter by Saddam's brutal regime. However,
the doctrine of humanitarian intervention cannot be applied retroactively
to morally justify war as a means of punishing a political leader
for past atrocities, such as Saddam's killing of more than 100,000
Kurds in the Anfal campaign, which occurred almost fifteen years
before the invasion. Because it is essentially a principle that
permits the defense of others, the doctrine of humanitarian intervention,
like the concept of self-defense, requires actually occurring
or imminent large-scale killing to justify the use of military
force. Criteria proposed in 2001 by an international commission
of legal scholars and practitioners would permit humanitarian
intervention to defend a vulnerable population from "large
scale loss of life" or "large scale 'ethnic cleansing"'
that is either actually "occurring" or "imminently
likely to occur.' Human Rights Watch, applying these criteria
to the Iraq war in its 2004 World Report, concludes, "That
was not the case in Saddam Hussein's Iraq in March 2003.... despite
the horrors of Saddam Hussein's rule, the invasion cannot be justified
as a humanitarian intervention."
Freedom and democracy for Iraq are "worth
fighting for, dying for and standing for."' President Bush
declared in a November 2003 speech, but no one asked the Iraqis
who were killed in the war whether they were willing to sacrifice
their lives as part of a demonstration project to create a democratic
revolution in the Middle East. The very minimum that people have
a right to expect from any effort to graft democracy onto their
nation is that the donor nation honor the principle of no extermination
without representation.
Denouncing the war a week after the invasion,
Kofi Annan, in an unusually candid interview with New York Times
reporter Felicity Barringer, said the UN Security Council authorized
"disarmament, not mass murder." American criminal law
defines murder as the purposeful or knowing killing of a human
being without justification or excuse. If, as the relevant law
and facts prove, the President's decision to invade Iraq cannot
be justified or excused as a war of liberation or an act of self-defense
or humanitarian intervention, then the killing of thousands of
innocent people in Iraq fits the legal definition of murder and
conspiracy to commit murder. While there are various legal and
political obstacles to actually prosecuting the President-either
in an international tribunal or an American court-we should not
shrink from saying that taking the country to war was the wrong
thing to do, not merely in the sense that the Administration's
prewar claims about WMD were "wrong," but in the same
sense in which mass murder is wrong.
"Each age and place has its own style
of evil," Time essayist Lance Morrow observes in his book
Evil: An Investigation. The history of radical evil up to now
has been primarily a story of world-class criminals, each with
his own method of mass killing, internment, expulsion and terror.
What is unique about the kind of evil the Bush Administration
has brought into the world is that a global law-enforcement campaign
to bring a world-class criminal to justice has itself become a
vast criminal enterprise. It is one of the bedrock principles
of the rule of law that a law-enforcement officer cannot break
the law as a means of enforcing the law. "For my part, I
think it is a less evil that some criminals should escape than
that the government should play an ignoble part," Holmes
wrote in a famous dissent that announced a constitutional principle
of "lesser evils" that would eventually become prevailing
law. The principle was most eloquently articulated by Justice
Louis Brandeis: "Our government is the potent, the omnipresent
teacher. For good or for ill, it teaches the whole people by its
example. Crime is contagious. If the government becomes a lawbreaker,
it breeds contempt for law; it invites every man to become a law
unto himself; it invites anarchy."
The capture of Saddam Hussein, who may
have killed as many as 300,000 people, ends a twenty-four-year
reign of terror and might finally bring a measure of justice to
the Iraqi people. But what would we think of a police chief whose
war against crime resulted in killing thousands of innocent bystanders
in the course of apprehending a criminal suspect, even a criminal
as despicable as Saddam? The officer who breaks the law, who becomes
a law unto himself, like the out-of-control cop played by Michael
Chiklis in the Fox cable drama The Shield-"Al Capone with
a badge," to borrow a line from the script-is more dangerous
than the criminal and, like the American guards who committed
the horrific abuses at Abu Ghraib prison, becomes a criminal himself.
The false charge that Saddam was reaching for his weapons of mass
destruction when US troops attacked bears an uncanny resemblance
to the pretexts for the use of deadly force that document a long
and shameful history of incidents of police misconduct in cities
across America. The evil of this President, once acclaimed for
his "moral clarity," is the evil of police violence
on a global scale-the evil of the law-enforcement officer who
regards himself as above the law and thereby undermines the very
foundation of law and morality.
If, in the 2004 presidential election
campaign, voters were to compel the candidates to confront the
profound moral and legal questions raised by the use of military
power that needlessly extinguished the lives of children, of entire
families, of great numbers of ordinary Iraqis who had as much
of a right to live as we do, there might ultimately emerge a nonpartisan
basis for a national consensus about the war, in much the same
way that a universal accord has developed in the United States
about the immorality and illegality of police conduct in violation
of an individual's civil liberties. While there will always be
disagreement about the way we should wage the war on terrorism,
as there will be about the way we should fight the war on crime,
a global form of law enforcement that unnecessarily kills thousands
of innocent people to punish or prevent crimes for which they
bear no responsibility is plainly and simply wrong.
Paul Savoy, a former assistant district
attorney for New York County and past dean of the John Kennedy
University School of Law in Pleasant Hill, California, is working
on a book about the Iraq war and what it can teach us about the
nature of evil.
Iraq page
Index
of Website
Home Page